Suicidio assistido
Assisted suicideWe need to clarify the current legal compromise but preserve the lenient attitude
The existing law on assisted suicide is contradictory, confused, and opaque. We need to take a fresh look at this issue and perhaps preserve the essence of the compromise that the courts tacitly favour.
Retired general practitioner Michael Irwin was recently investigated in the Isle of Man, for allegedly conspiring to assist the suicide of his friend Patrick Kneen.1 Irwin reportedly intended to provide a large dose of sleeping pills. Patricia, Mr Kneen's wife, was also investigated. In the event, neither was charged, which was surely a relief to both, given the prospect of a maximum prison sentence of 14 years, as would also be the case in England and Wales, under the Suicide Act 1961. The timing was arguably unfortunate, since the Manx Parliament (the House of Keys) is considering permitting voluntary euthanasia, a reform that Mr Kneen himself advocated publicly.
Our law lords have also recently contemplated—but rejected—both a similar proposal from Lord Joffe and the application by Diane Pretty.2-4 Mrs Pretty, who had motor neurone disease, sought an assurance that her husband would not be prosecuted should he assist in her suicide. Both our courts and the European Court of Human Rights denied that the right to life encompassed a right to choose the timing and manner of one's death. The judges also felt that any arguments premised on respect for patients' autonomy were outweighed by the state's interest in preserving life and protecting the vulnerable.
Diane Pretty's challenge and Lord Joffe's bill had the backing of the Voluntary Euthanasia Society, of which Irwin was chairman until the recent investigation. This is not the first time that one of its key personnel has allegedly breached the criminal law: the conviction of Nicholas Reed, the society's former general secretary, for assisted suicide prompted the organisation to change its name from EXIT, in order to distance itself from his activities.5 Then as now the organisation clearly stated that it does not condone operating outside the law, although it does seek a change in the law.
Surely a case is to be made for reform, but not along the permissive lines that have been proposed, including those in a controversial editorial in this journal.6 Rather, what is needed is greater clarity in the definition and application of the offence. The prosecutions to date in England and Wales show a body of law that is replete with uncertainty, obfuscation, and injustice.
Consider the "classic" case of "leaving the pills." Certainly convictions have been made in such circumstances, but this does not explain why one case was dismissed by the court since the accused "only provided the option," which was, said the judge, "not enough."7 Furthermore no health professional has been prosecuted for the offence in this jurisdiction despite at least anecdotal evidence indicating that such assistance does occur.8
No less confusing is the (il)legality of "death tourism." After Reginald Crew was assisted to die in Switzerland, uncertainty prevailed over whether his wife, Win, had committed an offence in helping him to travel there. Although the police declined to prosecute in that case, they have yet to promulgate their prosecuting policy on this issue.
Perhaps most objectionable, however, is a ruling reported in 1989. Mr and Mrs Johnson were convicted of assisting the suicide of their daughter Sara (who also had motor neurone disease) after she had taken an overdose. They did nothing positively to assist Sara: as the judge said they were guilty of "purely negative conduct" in sitting with her and honouring her request not to summon medical intervention.
That conviction is problematic for at least three reasons. Firstly, it implies that one must not inform one's close friends or relations as to any suicidal intent for fear of exposing them to criminality. That hardly sits well with the intentions behind the suicide bill, where it was stated that suicidal people should be dealt with compassionately (hence its decriminalisation).10 Secondly, supporters of the bill believed that the offence would require some "clear, positive element," so the Johnsons' convictions again seem to frustrate parliamentary intention.
But finally, and perhaps most importantly, in the healthcare context the conviction conflicts with the assumed validity of a patient's refusal of treatment, whether made contemporaneously or in advance of incompetence. Provided of course that Sara was competent (and perhaps that was the sticking point), she seemingly should have enjoyed the same rights as were successfully asserted by ventilator dependent Ms B.11 Yet, while Ms B's trust was found liable in damages for violating the principle of respect for a patient's autonomy and thereby trespassing against B, the Johnsons were found guilty for honouring that principle. What is the basis for the distinction? Is it simply because the Johnsons were not health professionals in a healthcare setting? Are advance directives valid only in such a context?
A case exists, at first sight, for a fresh look at this area. The current law rightly adopts a compromise between the more extreme "right to die" and right to life positions, as seen in those lenient sentences passed down on those (usually "mercy killers") convicted of the offence. Nevertheless, greater clarity is needed both here and in other aspects of the law governing the end(ing) of life. The best approach might be to heed recent calls for an investigation by a new House of Lords Select Committee or Royal Commission. Quite what shape the law will ultimately take remains to be seen; what should be clear, however, is that a review is desperately needed.
Richard Huxtable, lecturer in medical law and ethics
Centre for Ethics in Medicine, University of Bristol, Bristol BS2 8BH (R.Huxtable@bristol.ac.uk)
In: BMJ - Maio de 2004
<< Home